Many Rothbardians are
vowing not to vote in this or any election since voting only supports the
State. But I wonder if they could be persuaded otherwise if they knew one of
the ballot choices were to dissolve the governments and replace them with
voluntary market institutions. Of course, we don’t have that choice,
and most people would either laugh or be scared to death if it were proposed.
But with sovereign nations riding the Keynesian sled into the Abyss, the
dissolution might fall in our laps anyway. Preposterous as it might sound, we
might need to consider organizing society around something other than the
coercive monopolies driving us to extinction.
Fortunately, we have both experience and theory to draw upon. In this article
I want to touch on two sources from each: The classic study by Terry L.
Anderson and P. J. Hill, An American Experiment in Anarcho-Capitalism:
The Not So Wild, Wild West
and Robert P. Murphy’s Chaos Theory.
Thanks to Hollywood and popular literature, the American West
[1830-1900] is often portrayed as violent and lawless. As long as you had a
fast gun and were willing to use it, you could get away with anything. The
reason: weak or nonexistent government. In their literature search, though,
Anderson and Hill found ample evidence to the contrary. For example, W.
Eugene Hollon, in his book Frontier Violence:
Another Look found that “the Western frontier was a far more
civilized, more peaceful, and safer place than American society is today [the
early 1970s]." Another researcher, Frank Prassel,
writing in the mid-1930s, found that
if any conclusion
can be drawn from recent crime statistics, it must be that this last frontier
[the West] left no significant heritage of offenses against the person,
relative to other sections of the country.
In the early West people protected their property
and lives with private agencies. Significantly, these agencies understood
that violence was a costly method of resolving disputes and usually employed
lower-cost methods of settlement such as arbitration and courts. Nor was
there a universal idea of justice common to these agencies. People had
different ideas of what rules they wished to live under and were willing to
pay for. Competition among the agencies provided a choice.
Anderson and Hill looked at four institutions in the early West that
approximated anarcho-capitalism (AnCap): land claims clubs, cattlemen’s
associations, mining camps, and wagon trains.
Land Claims Clubs
Found throughout the Middle West, the land claims clubs or squatters’
associations showed how newly arriving pioneers joined together for common
purposes without government assistance.
Each claims association adopted its own constitution
and by-laws, elected officers for the operation of the organization,
established rules for adjudicating disputes, and established the procedure
for the registration and protection of claims.
Though violence was an option to be used against
those who didn’t follow the rules, at least one association used social
ostracism to curtail or punish violators. They formally resolved:
That we will not associate nor countenance those who
do not respect the claims of settlers and further that we will neither
neighbor with them . . . Trade barter deal with them in any way whatever.
Some claims associations were formed to oppose
“speculators,” while others encouraged speculation, exemplifying
how the clubs “developed rules consistent with the preferences, goals,
and endowments of the participants.”
Cattlemen’s Associations and Mining Camps
Like the claims groups, cattlemen’s associations drew up formal rules
governing their members, but their enforcement methods were often more
violent. As protection agencies, they hired gunfighters (stock detectives) to
eliminate rustlers. The mercenaries were not motivated by ethics, but by
“the side which made them the first or best offer.”
Did the gunslingers ever form criminal associations of their own, selling
protection and violating property rights as they wished? There were a few
loose associations of this kind, but they were “dealt with more quickly
and more severely under private property protective associations than under
government organization.”
The California gold rush of 1848 brought thousands of easterners west to seek
their fortune, as did gold discoveries later in Colorado, Montana, and Idaho.
Many gold seekers organized before leaving home, and as with other private
agencies the rules varied between organizations. People had the choice of
purchasing the set of rules they preferred. Interestingly, many of the mining
organizations prohibited lawyers from their districts and in one case
specified no more than fifty nor less than twenty lashes for lawyers who were
caught practicing law.
Anderson and Hill:
One early Californian writes, "We needed no law
until the lawyers came," and another adds, "There were few crimes
until the courts with their delays and technicalities took the place of
miners' law.”
Miners
courts provided a system of justice, and a judge and jury were selected from
among the members. Any law-abiding miner might serve as prosecutor or
defender of the accused.
In Colorado there is some evidence of competition
among the courts for business, and hence, an added guarantee
that justice prevailed.
Wagon Trains
Wagon trains rolling west in search of gold provide perhaps the best example
of anarcho-capitalism in the American frontier.
Realizing they would be passing beyond the pale of the law, the pioneers
“created their own law-making and law- enforcing machinery before they
started.” In many cases they created constitutions similar to the U.S.
Constitution. Once the travelers were beyond the jurisdiction of the federal
government, they elected officers to enforce the rules laid out in the
document.
The constitutions also included eligibility for
voting and decision rules for amendment, banishment of individuals from the
group, and dissolution of the company.
What made this arrangement work, according to the
authors, was a profound respect for property rights. Yet there was little
mention of property rights in their constitutions. The inviolability of
property rights was so throughly ingrained that the
pioneers rarely resorted to violence even when starvation was imminent.
Quoting John Phillip Reid from his study of the Overland Trail, the authors
tell us:
While a few of those who were destitute may have
employed tricks to obtain food, most begged, and those who were "too
proud to beg" got along the best they could or employed someone to beg
for them.
Certainly the transient nature of these rolling
communities made them more adaptable to anarcho-capitalism.
The demand for “public goods” such as roads or schools never came
up, for example, though they did have to protect themselves from Indian
attacks without relying on the State. For the most part, their arrangements
worked. People bought protection and justice, found competition among rules
producers, and the result was an orderly society, unlike that generally
associated with anarchy.
Murphy’s Case for Anarcho-Capitalism
In Chaos Theory, Robert P. Murphy sketches how market forces would
operate to support the private production of justice and defense -- two areas
that are traditionally conceded to be the sole province of the State. Murphy
contends that not only would the market be able to provide these services,
but would do so much more efficiently and equitably than the system we
have now.
Here, we’ll confine our discussion to a few key points he makes about
the production of “justice” on the free market.
As with the western pioneers and the world today, no single set of laws or
rules is needed to bind everyone. People would enter into voluntary contracts
that spell out the rules they agree to live by. “All aspects of social
intercourse would be ‘regulated’ by voluntary contracts.”
Who makes the rules? Private legal experts, who would draft laws under open
competition with rivals. The market deals with “justice” as it
does with other services. As Murphy notes,
“the market” is
just shorthand for the totality of economic interactions of freely acting
individuals. To allow the market to set legal rules really means that no one
uses violence to impose his own vision on everyone else.
In an advanced AnCap
society, insurance companies would play a major role. People would buy
policies, for example, to indemnify their victims if they were ever found
guilty of a crime. As they do now, insurance companies would employ experts
to determine the risks of insuring a given individual. If a person were
considered too great a risk he might be turned down, and this would be
information others would use in deciding if and how they wished to interact
with him.
Critics say this might work for peaceful, rational people but what about
incorrigible thieves and ax murderers? How would market anarchy deal with
them?
All Property is Privately Owned
Murphy reminds us that “wherever someone is standing in a purely
libertarian society, he would be on somebody’s property.” This
allows for force to be used against criminals without violating their natural
rights. He cites the example of a person entering a movie theater, with an
implicit contract such as the following:
If I am judged guilty of a crime by a reputable
arbitration agency [perhaps listed in an Appendix], I release the theater
owner from any liability should armed men come to remove me from his
property.
In this way the use of force would have been
authorized by the recipient himself beforehand.
But where do these armed men take the criminal? On a free market, a
high-security analog to jails would evolve. These jails, though, would
resemble hotels because they would be competing with each other for business,
which in AnCap means both pleasing the criminal and
guaranteeing his secure detention. Unlike government prisons there would be
no undue cruelty and virtually no chance of escape. If a dangerous criminal
escaped and killed again the insurance company would be held liable. And a
prisoner who didn’t like the way he was treated would have the option
of switching to a different jail, as long as his insurance company was in
agreement.
Would the Mafia Take Over?
People who support the State because they believe organized crime would take
control of an AnCap society should consider that
we’re already living under the “most ‘organized’
criminal association in human history.” Whatever crimes the Mafia has
committed, they are nothing -- nothing --
compared to the wanton death and destruction states have perpetrated.
We need to consider, too, that the mob gets its strength from the government,
not the free market.
All of the businesses traditionally associated with
organized crime—gambling, prostitution, loan sharking, drug
dealing—are prohibited or heavily regulated by the state. In market
anarchy, true professionals would drive out such unscrupulous competitors.
Applying AnCap
Murphy discusses several applications of anarcho-capitalism
in today’s world, one of which is medical licensing. Almost everyone
believes that without government regulation we would all be at the mercy of
quacks. “Ignorant consumers would go to whatever brain surgeon charged
the lowest price, and would be butchered on the operating table.”
Therefore, we need the iron fist of government to restrict entry into the
medical profession.
But this is pure fiction. Since the demand for safe and effective medicine is
universal, the market would respond accordingly with voluntary organizations
that would allow only qualified doctors into their ranks. Insurance
companies, too, would only underwrite doctors who met their standards, since
they would stand to lose millions in malpractice suits.
Regarding the ongoing controversy of gun control, Murphy sees legitimate
points to both sides of the debate:
Certainly we cannot trust the government to protect
us once it has disarmed us. But on the other hand, I feel a bit silly arguing
that people should be able to stockpile atomic weapons in their basement.
How might AnCap resolve
this? Let’s say Joe Smith wants an insurance company to agree to pay
$10 million to the estate of anyone Smith happens to kill. “The company
will be very interested to know whether Smith keeps sawed off
shotguns—let alone atomic weapons—in his basement.” In this
way truly dangerous weapons would be restricted to those willing to pay the
high premiums for owning them.
Though it’s hard to imagine any company willing to issue a policy to a
holder of nuclear weapons, nevertheless, if someone wanted to, there would be
no agency with the authority to prohibit owning them. But without a policy, a
person would be unable to guarantee his contracts with others and would find
it virtually impossible to function in society.
Getting there from here
Establishing an AnCap society depends heavily on
the history of the region. North Korean market anarchists, for example, might
have to use violence to curtail that brutal regime, while in the United
States, “a gradual and orderly erosion of the State is a wonderful
possibility.”
The one thing all such revolutions would share is a
commitment by the overwhelming majority to a total respect of property
rights.
People already understand that rape and murder are
crimes - even rapists and murderers. The hard part is convincing people
“that murder is wrong even when duly elected
‘representatives’ order it.”
We can build on intuitive notions of justice, just
as newly arriving miners in California respected the claims of earlier
settlers.
To take a more modern example, even inner city
toughs unthinkingly obey the “rules” in a pickup game of
basketball, despite the lack of a referee.
As he explains in a footnote, the players in a
pickup game still recognize the existence of a foul (and other rules), even
if the offending player denies he committed one.
Now, the market solution to such ambiguity and bias,
for games deemed important enough to warrant the extra cost and hassle, is to
appoint official referees to apply the “law” (which they too
unthinkingly respect). Notice that at no point is a violent monopoly needed
to achieve this orderly outcome.
Conclusion
Those who defend the State as necessary to protect property rights should
brush up on their history, from day one to the present. As Murphy wraps up,
I ask that the reader resist the temptation to
dismiss my ideas as “unworkable,” without first specifying in
what sense the government legal system “works.”
|