Vices Are Not Crimes: A Vindication of Moral Liberty
By Lysander Spooner (1875)
I
Vices are those acts by which a man harms himself or his
property.
Crimes are those acts by
which one man harms the person or property of another.
Vices are simply the
errors which a man makes in his search after his own happiness. Unlike
crimes, they imply no malice toward others, and no interference with their
persons or property.
In vices, the very essence of crime — that is, the design
to injure the person or property of another — is wanting.
It is a maxim of the law that there can be no crime
without a criminal intent; that is, without the intent to invade the person
or property of another. But no one ever practices a vice with any such
criminal intent. He practices his vice for his own happiness solely, and not
from any malice toward others.
Unless this clear distinction between vices and crimes be
made and recognized by the laws, there can be on earth no such thing as
individual right, liberty, or property — no such things as the right of one
man to the control of his own person and property, and the corresponding and
coequal rights of another man to the control of his own person and property.
For a government to declare a vice to be a crime, and to
punish it as such, is an attempt to falsify the very nature of things. It is
as absurd as it would be to declare truth to be falsehood, or falsehood
truth.
II
Every voluntary act of a man's life is either virtuous or
vicious. That is to say, it is either in accordance, or in conflict, with
those natural laws of matter and mind on which his physical, mental, and
emotional health and well-being depend. In other words, every act of his life
tends, on the whole, either to his happiness, or to his unhappiness. No
single act in his whole existence is indifferent.
Furthermore, each human being differs in his physical,
mental, and emotional constitution, and also in the circumstances by which he
is surrounded, from every other human being. Many acts, therefore, that are
virtuous, and tend to happiness, in the case of one person, are vicious, and
tend to unhappiness, in the case of another person.
Many acts, also, that are virtuous, and tend to
happiness, in the case of one man, at one time, and under one set of
circumstances, are vicious, and tend to unhappiness, in the case of the same
man, at another time, and under other circumstances.
III
To know what actions are virtuous, and what vicious — in
other words, to know what actions tend, on the whole, to happiness, and what
to unhappiness — in the case of each and every man, in each and all the
conditions in which they may severally be placed, is the profoundest and most
complex study to which the greatest human mind ever has been, or ever can be,
directed. It is, nevertheless, the constant study to which each and every man
— the humblest in intellect as well as the greatest — is necessarily
driven by the desires and necessities of his own existence. It is also
the study in which each and every person, from his cradle to his grave, must
necessarily form his own conclusions — because no one else knows or feels, or
can know or feel, as he knows and feels the desires and necessities, the
hopes, and fears, and impulses of his own nature, or the pressure of his own
circumstances.
IV
It is not often possible to say of those acts that are
called vices, that they really are vices, except in degree. That is, it is
difficult to say of any actions, or courses of action, that are called vices,
that they really would have been vices, if they had stopped short of a
certain point. The question of virtue or vice, therefore, in all such cases,
is a question of quantity and degree, and not of the intrinsic character of
any single act, by itself. This fact adds to the difficulty, not to say the
impossibility, of any one's — except each individual for himself — drawing
any accurate line, or anything like any accurate line, between virtue and
vice — that is, of telling where virtue ends, and vice begins. And this is
another reason why this whole question of virtue and vice should be left for
each person to settle for himself.
V
Vices are usually pleasurable, at least for the time
being, and often do not disclose themselves as vices by their effects until
after they have been practiced for many years, perhaps for a lifetime. To
many, perhaps most, of those who practice them, they do not disclose themselves
as vices at all during life.
Virtues, on the other hand, often appear so harsh and
rugged, they require the sacrifice of so much present happiness, at least,
and the results, which alone prove them to be virtues, are often so distant
and obscure, in fact, so absolutely invisible to the minds of many,
especially of the young, that, from the very nature of things, there can be
no universal, or even general, knowledge that they are virtues. In truth, the
studies of profound philosophers have been expended — if not wholly in vain,
certainly with very small results — in efforts to draw the lines between the
virtues and the vices.
If, then, it became so difficult, so nearly impossible,
in most cases, to determine what is, and what is not, vice — and especially
if it be so difficult, in nearly all cases, to determine where virtue ends,
and vice begins — and if these questions, which no one can really and truly
determine for anybody but himself, are not to be left free and open for
experiment by all, each person is deprived of the highest of all his rights
as a human being, to wit, his right to inquire, investigate, reason, try
experiments, judge, and ascertain for himself what is, to him,
virtue, and what is, to him, vice — in other words: what, on the
whole, conduces to his happiness, and what, on the whole, tends to
his unhappiness. If this great right is not to be left free and open to
all, then each man's whole right, as a reasoning human being, to
"liberty and the pursuit of happiness," is denied him.
VI
We all come into the world in ignorance of ourselves, and
of everything around us. By a fundamental law of our natures we are all
constantly impelled by the desire of happiness, and the fear of pain. But we
have everything to learn, as to what will give us happiness, and save us from
pain. No two of us are wholly alike, either physically, mentally, or
emotionally — or, consequently, in our physical, mental, or emotional
requirements for the acquisition of happiness and the avoidance of
unhappiness.
No one of us, therefore, can learn this indispensable
lesson of happiness and unhappiness, of virtue and vice, for another. Each
must learn it for himself. To learn it, he must be at liberty to try all
experiments that commend themselves to his judgment.
Some of his experiments succeed, and, because they
succeed, are called virtues; others fail, and, because they fail, are called
vices. He gathers wisdom as much from his failures as from his successes;
from his so-called vices, as from his so-called virtues. Both are necessary
to his acquisition of that knowledge — of his own nature, and of the world
around him, and of their adaptations or nonadaptations to each other — which
shall show him how happiness is acquired, and pain avoided. And, unless he
can be permitted to try these experiments to his own satisfaction, he is
restrained from the acquisition of knowledge, and, consequently, from
pursuing the great purpose and duty of his life.
VII
A man is under no obligation to take anybody's word, or
yield to anybody's authority, on a matter so vital to himself, and in regard
to which no one else has, or can have, any such interest as he. He cannot,
if he would, safely rely upon the opinions of other men, because he finds
that the opinions of other men do not agree.
Certain actions, or courses of action, have been
practiced by many millions of men, through successive generations, and have
been held by them to be, on the whole, conducive to happiness, and therefore
virtuous. Other men, in other ages or countries, or under other conditions,
have held, as the result of their experience and observation, that these
actions tended, on the whole, to unhappiness, and were therefore vicious.
The question of virtue or vice, as already remarked in a
previous section, has also been, in most minds, a question of degree — that
is, of the extent to which certain actions should be carried — and not of the
intrinsic character of any single act by itself. The questions of virtue and
vice have therefore been as various, and, in fact, as infinite, as the
varieties of mind, body, and condition of the different individuals
inhabiting the globe. And the experience of ages has left an infinite number
of these questions unsettled. In fact, it can scarcely be said to have
settled any of them.
VIII
In the midst of this endless variety of opinion, what
man, or what body of men, has the right to say, in regard to any particular
action, or course of action, "We have tried this experiment,
and determined every question involved in it. We have determined it,
not only for ourselves, but for all others. And, as to all those who are
weaker than we, we will coerce them to act in obedience to our conclusion. We
will suffer no further experiment or inquiry by any one, and, consequently,
no further acquisition of knowledge by anybody"?
Who are the men who have the right to say this? Certainly
there are none such. The men who really do say it are either shameless
impostors and tyrants, who would stop the progress of knowledge, and usurp
absolute control over the minds and bodies of their fellow men — and are
therefore to be resisted instantly, and to the last extent — or they are
themselves too ignorant of their own weaknesses, and of their true relations
to other men, to be entitled to any other consideration than sheer pity or
contempt.
"It is a natural impossibility that
a government should have a right to punish men for their vices; because it is
impossible that a government should have any rights except such as the
individuals composing it had previously had as individuals."
We know, however, that there are such men as these in the
world. Some of them attempt to exercise their power only within a small
sphere, to wit, upon their children, their neighbors, their townsmen, and
their countrymen. Others attempt to exercise it on a larger scale.
For example, an old man at Rome, aided by a few
subordinates, attempts to decide all questions of virtue and vice — that is,
of truth or falsehood, especially in matters of religion. He claims to know
and teach what religious ideas and practices are conducive, or fatal, to a
man's happiness, not only in this world, but in that which is to come. He
claims to be miraculously inspired for the performance of this work — thus
virtually acknowledging, like a sensible man, that nothing short of
miraculous inspiration would qualify him for it.
This miraculous inspiration, however, has been
ineffectual to enable him to settle more than a very few questions. The most
important to which common mortals can attain is an implicit belief in his
(the pope's) infallibility! and, secondly, that the blackest vices of
which they can be guilty are to believe and declare that he is only a man
like the rest of them!
It required some 1500 or 1800 years to enable him to
reach definite conclusions on these two vital points. Yet it would seem that
the first of these must necessarily be preliminary to his settlement of any
other questions; because, until his own infallibility is determined, he can
authoritatively decide nothing else.
He has, however, heretofore attempted or pretended to
settle a few others. And he may, perhaps, attempt or pretend to settle a few
more in the future, if he shall continue to find anybody to listen to him.
But his success, thus far, certainly does not encourage the belief that he
will be able to settle all questions of virtue and vice, even in his peculiar
department of religion, in time to meet the necessities of mankind.
He, or his successors, will undoubtedly be compelled, at
no distant day, to acknowledge that he has undertaken a task to which all his
miraculous inspiration was inadequate; and that, of necessity, each human
being must be left to settle all questions of this kind for himself. And it
is not unreasonable to expect that all other popes, in other and lesser
spheres, will some time have cause to come to the same conclusion.
No one, certainly, not claiming supernatural inspiration,
should undertake a task to which obviously nothing less than such inspiration
is adequate. And, clearly, no one should surrender his own judgment to the
teachings of others, unless he be first convinced that these others have
something more than ordinary human knowledge on this subject.
If those persons, who fancy themselves gifted with both
the power and the right to define and punish other men's vices, would but
turn their thoughts inwardly, they would probably find that they have a great
work to do at home — and that, when that shall have been completed, they will
be little disposed to do more toward correcting the vices of others than
simply to give to others the results of their experience and observation. In
this sphere their labors may possibly be useful; but, in the sphere of
infallibility and coercion, they will probably, for well-known reasons, meet
with even less success in the future than such men have met with in the past.
IX
It is now obvious, from the reasons already given, that
government would be utterly impracticable, if it were to take cognizance of
vices and punish them as crimes. Every human being has his or her vices.
Nearly all men have a great many. And they are of all kinds — physiological,
mental, emotional, religious, social, commercial, industrial, economical,
etc., etc. If government is to take cognizance of any of these vices, and
punish them as crimes, then, to be consistent, it must take cognizance of
all, and punish all impartially.
The consequence would be that everybody would be in
prison for his or her vices. There would be no one left outside to lock the
doors upon those within. In fact, courts enough could not be found to try the
offenders, nor prisons enough built to hold them. All human industry in the
acquisition of knowledge, and even in acquiring the means of subsistence,
would be arrested: for we should all be under constant trial or imprisonment
for our vices. But even if it were possible to imprison all the vicious, our
knowledge of human nature tells us that, as a general rule, they would be far
more vicious in prison than they ever have been out of it.
X
A government that shall punish all vices impartially is
so obviously an impossibility that nobody was ever found, or ever will be
found, foolish enough to propose it. The most that any one proposes is, that
government shall punish some one, or at most a few, of what he esteems the
grossest of them. But this discrimination is an utterly absurd, illogical,
and tyrannical one. What right has any body of men to say, "The vices of
other men we will punish; but our own vices nobody shall punish. We
will restrain other men from seeking their own happiness according to their
own notions of it; but nobody shall restrain us from seeking our own
happiness according to our own notions of it. We will restrain other
men from acquiring any experimental knowledge of what is conducive or necessary
to their own happiness; but nobody shall restrain us from acquiring
an experimental knowledge of what is conducive or necessary to our own
happiness"?
Nobody but knaves or blockheads ever thinks of making
such absurd assumptions as these. And yet, evidently, it is only upon such
assumptions that anybody can claim the right to punish the vices of others,
and at the same time claim exemption from punishment for his own.
XI
Such a thing as a government formed by voluntary
association would never have been thought of if the object proposed had been
the punishment of all vices impartially; because nobody wants such an
institution, or would voluntarily submit to it. But a government formed by voluntary
association for the punishment of all crimes is a reasonable matter;
because everybody wants protection for himself against all crimes by others,
and also acknowledges the justice of his own punishment, if he commits a
crime.
XII
It is a natural impossibility that a government should
have a right to punish men for their vices; because it is impossible
that a government should have any rights except such as the individuals
composing it had previously had as individuals. They could not
delegate to a government any rights they did not themselves possess. They
could not contribute to the government any rights, except such as
they themselves possessed as individuals.
Now, nobody but a fool or an impostor pretends that he,
as an individual, has a right to punish other men for their vices. But
anybody and everybody have a natural right, as individuals, to
punish other men for their crimes; for everybody has a natural right, not
only to defend his own person and property against aggressors, but also to go
to the assistance and defense of everybody else whose person or property is
invaded.
The natural right of each individual to defend his own
person and property against an aggressor, and to go to the assistance and
defense of everyone else whose person or property is invaded, is a right
without which men could not exist on the earth. And government has no
rightful existence, except in so far as it embodies, and is limited by, this
natural right of individuals.
But the idea that each man has a natural right to decide
what are virtues, and what are vices — that is, what contributes to that
neighbor's happiness, and what do not — and to punish him for all that do not
contribute to it, is what no one ever had the impudence or folly to assert.
It is only those who claim that government has some rightful power,which no
individual or individuals ever did, or could, delegate to it, that claim that
government has any rightful power to punish vices.
It will do for a pope or a king — who claims to have
received direct authority from Heaven to rule over his fellowmen — to claim
the right, as the vicegerent of God, to punish men for their vices; but it is
a sheer and utter absurdity for any government, claiming to derive its power
wholly from the grant of the governed, to claim any such power; because
everybody knows that the governed never would grant it. For them to grant it
would be an absurdity, because it would be granting away their own right to
seek their own happiness; since to grant away their right to judge of what will
be for their happiness is to grant away all their right to pursue their own
happiness.
XIII
We can now see how simple, easy, and reasonable a matter
a government is for the punishment of crimes, as compared with one
for the punishment of vices. Crimes are few, and easily
distinguished from all other acts; and mankind are generally agreed as to
what acts are crimes. Whereas vices are innumerable; and no two persons are
agreed, except in comparatively few cases, as to what are vices.
Furthermore, everybody wishes to be protected,
in his person and property, against the aggressions of other men. But nobody
wishes to be protected, either in his person or property, against himself;
because it is contrary to the fundamental laws of human nature itself that
any one should wish to harm himself. He only wishes to promote his own
happiness, and to be his own judge as to what will promote, and does promote,
his own happiness.
This is what every one wants, and has a right to, as a
human being. And though we all make many mistakes, and necessarily must make
them, from the imperfection of our knowledge, yet these mistakes are no
argument against the right; because they all tend to give us the very
knowledge we need, and are in pursuit of, and can get in no other way.
The object aimed at in the punishment of crimes,
therefore, is not only wholly different from, but it is directly opposed to,
that aimed at in the punishment of vices.
The object aimed at in the punishment of crimes
is to secure, to each and every man alike, the fullest liberty he possibly
can have — consistently with the equal rights of others — to pursue his own
happiness, under the guidance of his own judgment, and by the use of his own
property. On the other hand, the object aimed at in the punishment of vices
is to deprive every man of his natural right and liberty to pursue
his own happiness under the guidance of his own judgment and by the use of
his own property.
These two objects, then, are directly opposed to each
other. They are as directly opposed to each other as are light and darkness,
or as truth and falsehood, or as liberty and slavery. They are utterly
incompatible with each other; and to suppose the two to be embraced in one
and the same government is an absurdity, an impossibility. It is to suppose
the objects of a government to be to commit crimes, and to prevent crimes —
to destroy individual liberty, and to secure individual liberty.
XIV
Finally, on this point of individual liberty, every man must
necessarily judge and determine for himself as to what is conducive and
necessary to, and what is destructive of, his own well-being; because, if he
omits to perform this task for himself, nobody else can perform it for him.
And nobody else will even attempt to perform it for him, except in very few cases.
Popes, and priests, and kings will assume to perform it for him, in certain
cases, if permitted to do so. But they will, in general, perform it only in
so far as they can minister to their own vices and crimes by doing it. They
will, in general, perform it only in so far as they can make him their fool
and their slave.
Parents, with better motives, no doubt, than the others,
too often attempt the same work. But in so far as they practice coercion, or
restrain a child from anything not really and seriously dangerous to himself,
they do him a harm, rather than a good. It is a law of Nature that to get
knowledge, and to incorporate that knowledge into his own being, each
individual must get it for himself. Nobody, not even his parents, can tell
him the nature of fire, so that he will really know it. He must himself
experiment with it, and be burnt by it, before he can know it.
Nature knows, a thousand times better than any parent,
what she designs each individual for, what knowledge he requires, and how he
must get it. She knows that her own processes for communicating that
knowledge are not only the best, but the only ones that can be effectual.
The attempts of parents to make their children virtuous
are generally little else than attempts to keep them in ignorance of vice.
They are little else than attempts to teach their children to know and prefer
truth by keeping them in ignorance of falsehood. They are little else than
attempts to make them seek and appreciate health by keeping them in ignorance
of disease and of everything that will cause disease. They are little else
than attempts to make their children love the light by keeping them in
ignorance of darkness. In short, they are little else than attempts to make
their children happy by keeping them in ignorance of everything that causes
them unhappiness.
In so far as parents can really aid their children in the
latter's search after happiness, by simply giving them the results of their
(the parents') own reason and experience, it is all very well, and is a
natural and appropriate duty. But to practice coercion in matters of which
the children are reasonably competent to judge for themselves is only an
attempt to keep them in ignorance.
And this is as much a tyranny, and as much a violation of
the children's right to acquire knowledge for themselves, and such knowledge
as they desire, as is the same coercion when practiced upon older persons.
Such coercion, practiced upon children, is a denial of their right to develop
the faculties that Nature has given them, and to be what Nature designs them
to be. It is a denial of their right to themselves, and to the use of their
own powers. It is a denial of their right to acquire the most valuable of all
knowledge, to wit, the knowledge that Nature, the great teacher, stands ready
to impart to them.
The results of such coercion are not to make the children
wise or virtuous, but to make them ignorant, and consequently weak and
vicious — and to perpetuate through them, from age to age, the ignorance, the
superstitions, the vices, and the crimes of the parents. This is proved by
every page of the world's history.
Those who hold opinions opposite to these are those whose
false and vicious theologies, or whose own vicious general ideas, have taught
them that the human race are naturally given to evil, rather than good; to
the false, rather than the true; that mankind do not naturally turn their
eyes to the light; that they love darkness rather than light; and that they
find their happiness only in those things that tend to their misery.
XV
But these men, who claim that government shall use its
power to prevent vice, will say, or are in the habit of saying, "We
acknowledge the right of an individual to seek his own happiness in his own
way, and consequently to be as vicious as he pleases; we only claim that
government shall prohibit the sale to him of those articles by which
he ministers to his vice."
The answer to this is that the simple sale of any article
whatever — independently of the use that is to be made of the article — is
legally a perfectly innocent act. The quality of the act of sale depends
wholly upon the quality of the use for which the thing is sold. If the use of
anything is virtuous and lawful, then the sale of it, for that use,
is virtuous and lawful. If the use is vicious, then the sale of it, for
that use, is vicious. If the use is criminal, then the sale of it, for
that use, is criminal.
The seller is, at most, only an accomplice in the use
that is to be made of the article sold, whether the use be virtuous, vicious,
or criminal. Where the use is criminal, the seller is an accomplice in the
crime, and punishable as such. But where the use is only vicious, the seller
is only an accomplice in the vice, and is not punishable.
XVI
But it will be asked, "Is there no right, on the
part of government, to arrest the progress of those who are bent on
self-destruction?"
The answer is that government has no rights whatever in
the matter, so long as these so-called vicious persons remain sane, compos
mentis, capable of exercising reasonable discretion and self-control.
Because, so long as they do remain sane, they must be allowed to judge and
decide for themselves whether their so-called vices really are vices; whether
they really are leading them to destruction; and whether, on the whole, they
will go there or not.
When they shall become insane, non compos mentis,
incapable of reasonable discretion or self-control, their friends or
neighbors, or the government, must take care of them, and protect them from
harm, and against all persons who would do them harm, in the same way as if
their insanity had come upon them from any other cause than their supposed
vices.
But because a man is supposed, by his neighbors, to be on
the way to self-destruction from his vices, it does not, therefore, follow
that he is insane, non compos mentis, incapable of reasonable
discretion and self-control, within the legal meaning of those terms. Men and
women may be addicted to very gross vices, and to a great many of them — such
as gluttony, drunkenness, prostitution, gambling, prize fighting, tobacco
chewing, smoking, and snuffing, opium eating, corset wearing, idleness, waste
of property, avarice, hypocrisy, etc., etc. — and still be sane, compos
mentis, capable of reasonable discretion and self-control, within the
meaning of the law.
"The object aimed at in the
punishment of vices is to deprive every man of his natural right and liberty
to pursue his own happiness under the guidance of his own judgment and by the
use of his own property."
And so long as they are sane, they must be permitted to
control themselves and their property, and to be their own judges as to where
their vices will finally lead them. It may be hoped by the lookers-on, in
each individual case, that the vicious person will see the end to which he is
tending, and be induced to turn back.
But if he chooses to go on to what other men call
destruction, he must be permitted to do so. And all that can be said of him,
so far as this life is concerned, is that he made a great mistake in his
search after happiness, and that others will do well to take warning by his
fate. As to what may be his condition in another life, that is a theological
question with which the law, in this world, has no more to do than it has
with any other theological question, touching men's condition in a future
life.
If it be asked how the question of a vicious man's sanity
or insanity is to be determined, the answer is that it is to be determined by
the same kinds of evidence as is the sanity or insanity of those who are
called virtuous, and not otherwise. That is, by the same kinds of evidence by
which the legal tribunals determine whether a man should be sent to an asylum
for lunatics, or whether he is competent to make a will, or otherwise dispose
of his property. Any doubt must weigh in favor of his sanity, as in all other
cases, and not of his insanity.
If a person really does become insane, non compos
mentis, incapable of reasonable discretion or self-control, it is then a
crime on the part of other men, to give to him or sell to him the means of
self-injury.[1] There are no crimes more easily punished, no cases in which
juries would be more ready to convict, than those where a sane person should
sell or give to an insane one any article with which the latter was likely to
injure himself.
XVII
But it will be said that some men are made by their vices
dangerous to other persons; that a drunkard, for example, is sometimes
quarrelsome and dangerous toward his family or others. And it will be asked,
"Has the law nothing to do in such a case?"
The answer is that if, either from drunkenness or any
other cause, a man be really dangerous, either to his family or to other
persons, not only himself may be rightfully restrained, so far as the safety
of other persons requires, but all other persons — who know or have
reasonable grounds to believe him dangerous — may also be restrained from
selling or giving to him anything that they have reason to suppose will make
him dangerous.
But because one man becomes quarrelsome and dangerous
after drinking spirituous liquors, and because it is a crime to give or sell
liquor to such a man, it does not follow at all that it is a crime to sell
liquors to the hundreds and thousands of other persons who are not made
quarrelsome or dangerous by drinking them. Before a man can be convicted of
crime in selling liquor to a dangerous man, it must be shown that the
particular man, to whom the liquor was sold, was dangerous; and also that the
seller knew, or had reasonable grounds to suppose, that the man would be made
dangerous by drinking it.
The presumption of law is, in all cases, that the sale is
innocent; and the burden of proving it criminal, in any particular case,
rests upon the government. And that particular case must be proved criminal,
independentlyof all others.
Subject to these principles, there is no difficulty
convicting and punishing men for the sale or gift of any article to a man,
who is made dangerous to others by the use of it.
XVIII
But it is often said that some vices are nuisances
(public or private), and that nuisances can be abated and punished.
It is true that anything that is really and legally a
nuisance (either public or private) can be abated and punished. But it is not
true that the mere private vices of one man are, in any legal sense,
nuisances to another man or to the public.
No act of one person can be a nuisance to another unless
it in some way obstructs or interferes with that other's safe and quiet use
or enjoyment of what is rightfully his own.
Whatever obstructs a public highway is a nuisance and may
be abated and punished. But a hotel where liquors are sold, a liquor store,
or even a grog shop, so called, no more obstructs a public highway, than does
a dry goods store, a jewelry store, or a butcher's shop.
Whatever poisons the air, or makes it either offensive or
unhealthful, is a nuisance. But neither a hotel, nor a liquor store, nor a
grog shop poisons the air, or makes it offensive or unhealthful to outside
persons.
Whatever obstructs the light, to which a man is legally
entitled, is a nuisance. But neither a hotel, nor a liquor store, nor a grog
shop, obstructs anybody's light, except in cases where a church, a
schoolhouse, or a dwelling house would have equally obstructed it. On this
ground, therefore, the former are no more, and no less, nuisances than the
latter would be.
Some persons are in the habit of saying that a liquor
shop is dangerous, in the same way that gunpowder is dangerous. But there is
no analogy between the two cases. Gunpowder is liable to be exploded by
accident, and especially by such fires as often occur in cities. For these
reasons it is dangerous to persons and property in its immediate vicinity.
But liquors are not liable to be thus exploded, and therefore are not
dangerous nuisances, in any such sense as is gunpowder in cities.
But it is said, again, that drinking places are
frequently filled with noisy and boisterous men, who disturb the quiet of the
neighborhood, and the sleep and rest of the neighbors.
This may be true occasionally, though not very
frequently. But whenever, in any case, it is true, the nuisance may be abated
by the punishment of the proprietor and his customers, and if need be, by
shutting up the place. But an assembly of noisy drinkers is no more a
nuisance than is any other noisy assembly.
A jolly or hilarious drinker disturbs the quiet of a
neighborhood no more, and no less, than does a shouting religious fanatic. An
assembly of noisy drinkers is no more, and no less, a nuisance than is an
assembly of shouting religious fanatics. Both of them are nuisances when they
disturb the rest and sleep, or quiet, of neighbors. Even a dog that is given
to barking, to the disturbance of the sleep or quiet of the neighborhood, is
a nuisance.
XIX
But it is said that for one person to entice another into
a vice is a crime.
This is preposterous. If any particular act is simply a vice,
then a man who entices another to commit it, is simply an accomplice in the
vice. He evidently commits no crime, because the accomplice can
certainly commit no greater offence than the principal.
Every person who is sane, compos mentis,
possessed of reasonable discretion and self-control, is presumed to be
mentally competent to judge for himself of all the arguments, pro and
con, that may be addressed to him, to persuade him to do any particular
act, provided no fraud is employed to deceive him. And if he is
persuaded or induced to do the act, his act is then his own; and even though
the act prove to be harmful to himself, he cannot complain that the
persuasion or arguments, to which he yielded his assent, were crimes against
himself.
When fraud is practiced, the case is, of course,
different. If, for example, I offer a man poison, assuring him that it is a
safe and wholesome drink, and he, on the faith of my assertion, swallows it,
my act is a crime.
Volenti non fit injuria,
is a maxim of the law. "To the willing, no injury is done." That
is, no legal wrong. And every person who is sane, compos mentis,
capable of exercising reasonable discretion in judging of the truth or
falsehood of the representations or persuasion to which he yields his assent,
is "willing," in the view of the law; and takes upon himself the
entire responsibility for his acts, when no intentional fraud has been
practiced upon him.
This principle, that to the willing no injury is done,
has no limit, except in the case of frauds, or of persons not possessed of
reasonable discretion for judging in the particular case. If a person
possessed of reasonable discretion, and not deceived by fraud, consents to
practice the grossest vice, and thereby brings upon himself the greatest
moral, physical, or pecuniary sufferings or losses, he cannot allege that he
has been legally wronged.
To illustrate this principle, take the case of rape. To
have carnal knowledge of a woman, against her will, is the highest
crime, next to murder, that can be committed against her. But to have carnal
knowledge of her, with her consent, is no crime but, at most, a
vice. And it is usually holden that a female child, of no more than ten
years of age, has such reasonable discretion, that her consent, even though
procured by rewards, or promises of reward, is sufficient to convert the act,
which would otherwise be a high crime, into a simple act of vice.[2]
We see the same principle in the case of prize fighters.
If I but lay one of my fingers upon another man's person, against his
will, no matter how lightly, and no matter how little practical injury
is done, the act is a crime. But if two men agree to go out and
pound each other's faces to a jelly, it is no crime, but only a vice.
Even duels have not generally been considered crimes,
because each man's life is his own, and the parties agree that each
may take the other's life, if he can, by the use of such weapons as are
agreed upon, and in conformity with certain rules that are also mutually
assented to.
And this is a correct view of the matter, unless it can
be said (as it probably cannot), that "anger is a madness" that so
far deprives men of their reason as to make them incapable of reasonable
discretion.
Gambling is another illustration of the principle that to
the willing no injury is done. If I take but a single cent of a man's
property, without his consent, the act is a crime. But if two men,
who are compos mentis, possessed of reasonable discretion to judge
of the nature and probable results of their act, sit down together, and each
voluntarily stakes his money against the money of another, on the turn of a
die, and one of them loses his whole estate (however large that may be), it
is no crime, but only a vice.
It is not a crime, even, to assist a person to commit
suicide, if he be in possession of his reason.
It is a somewhat common idea that suicide is, of itself,
conclusive evidence of insanity. But, although it may ordinarily be very
strong evidence of insanity, it is by no means conclusive in all cases. Many
persons, in undoubted possession of their reason, have committed suicide to
escape the shame of a public exposure for their crimes, or to avoid some
other great calamity. Suicide, in these cases, may not have been the highest
wisdom, but it certainly was not proof of any lack of reasonable discretion.[3]
And being within the limits of reasonable discretion, it
was no crime for other persons to aid it, either by furnishing the instrument
or otherwise. And if, in such cases, it be no crime to aid a suicide, how
absurd to say that it is a crime to aid him in some act that is really
pleasurable, and which a large portion of mankind have believed to be useful?
XX
But some persons are in the habit of saying that the use
of spirituous liquors is the great source of crime, that "it
fills our prisons with criminals," and that this is reason enough for
prohibiting the sale of them.
Those who say this, if they talk seriously, talk blindly
and foolishly. They evidently mean to be understood as saying that a very
large percentage of all the crimes that are committed among men, are committed
by persons whose criminal passions are excited, at the time, by the
use of liquors, and in consequence of the use of liquors.
This idea is utterly preposterous.
In the first place, the great crimes committed in the
world are mostly prompted by avarice and ambition.
The greatest of all crimes are the wars that are carried
on by governments to plunder, enslave, and destroy mankind.
The next greatest crimes committed in the world are
equally prompted by avarice and ambition; and are committed, not on sudden
passion, but by men of calculation, who keep their heads cool and clear, and
who have no thought whatever of going to prison for them.
They are committed, not so much by men who violate
the laws, as by men who, either by themselves or by their instruments, make
the laws — by men who have combined to usurp arbitrary power, and to maintain
it by force and fraud, and whose purpose in usurping and maintaining it is by
unjust and unequal legislation, to secure to themselves such advantages and
monopolies as will enable them to control and extort the labor and properties
of other men, and thus impoverish them, in order to minister to their own
wealth and aggrandizement.[4] The robberies and wrongs thus
committed by these men, in conformity with the laws — that is, their
own laws — are as mountains to molehills, compared with the crimes
committed by all other criminals, in violation of the laws.
But, thirdly, there are vast numbers of frauds of various
kinds committed in the transactions of trade, whose perpetrators, by their
coolness and sagacity, evade the operation of the laws. And it is only their
cool and clear heads that enable them to do it. Men under the excitement of
intoxicating drinks are little disposed, and utterly unequal, to the
successful practice of these frauds. They are the most incautious, the least
successful, the least efficient, and the least to be feared, of all the
criminals with whom the laws have to deal.
Fourthly, the professed burglars, robbers, thieves,
forgers, counterfeiters, and swindlers who prey upon society are anything but
reckless drinkers. Their business is of too dangerous a character to admit of
such risks as they would thus incur.
"Men can endure but a certain amount
of misery before their hope and courage fail and they yield to almost
anything that promises present relief or mitigation — though at the cost of
still greater misery in the future."
Fifthly, the crimes that can be said to be committed
under the influence of intoxicating drinks are mostly assaults and batteries,
not very numerous, and generally not very aggravated. Some other small
crimes, as petty thefts, or other small trespasses upon property, are
sometimes committed under the influence of drink by feebleminded persons, not
generally addicted to crime. The persons who commit these two kinds of crime
are but few. They cannot be said to "fill our prisons"; or, if they
do, we are to be congratulated that we need so few prisons and so small
prisons to hold them.
The State of Massachusetts, for example, has a million
and a half of people. How many of these are now in prison for crimes
— not for the vice of intoxication, but for crimes — committed
against persons or property under the instigation of strong drink? I doubt if
there be one in ten thousand, that is, one hundred and fifty in all; and the
crimes for which these are in prison are mostly very small ones.
And I think it will be found that these few men are
generally much more to be pitied than punished, for the reason that it was
their poverty and misery, rather than any passion for liquor or for crime,
that led them to drink, and thus led them to commit their crimes under the
influence of drink.
The sweeping charge that drink "fills our prisons
with criminals" is made, I think, only by those men who know no better
than to call a drunkard a criminal; and who have no better foundation for
their charge than the shameful fact that we are such a brutal and senseless
people that we condemn and punish such weak and unfortunate persons as
drunkards as if they were criminals.
The legislators who authorize, and the judges who
practice, such atrocities as these, are intrinsically criminals; unless their
ignorance be such — as it probably is not — as to excuse them. And, if they
were themselves to be punished as criminals, there would be more reason in
our conduct.
A police judge in Boston once told me that he was in the
habit of disposing of drunkards (by sending them to prison for thirty days —
I think that was the stereotyped sentence) at the rate of one in three
minutes, and sometimes more rapidly even than that — thus condemning
them as criminals, and sending them to prison without mercy and without
inquiry into circumstances, for an infirmity that entitled them to compassion
and protection, instead of punishment. The real criminals in these
cases were not the men who went to prison, but the judge, and the men behind
him, who sent them there.
I recommend to these persons, who are so distressed lest the prisons of Massachusetts
be filled with criminals, that they employ some portion, at least, of their
philanthropy in preventing our prisons being filled with persons who are not
criminals. I do not remember to have heard that their sympathies have
ever been very actively exercised in that direction.
On the contrary, they seem to have such a passion for punishing criminals,
that they care not to inquire particularly whether a candidate for punishment
really be a criminal. Such a passion, let me assure them, is a much more
dangerous one, and one entitled to far less charity, both morally and
legally, than the passion for strong drink.
It seems to be much more consonant with the merciless character of these
men to send an unfortunate man to prison for drunkenness and thus crush and
degrade and dishearten him and ruin him for life, than it does for them to
lift him out of the poverty and misery that caused him to become a drunkard.
It is only those persons who have either little capacity, or little
disposition, to enlighten, encourage, or aid mankind, that are possessed of
this violent passion for governing, commanding, and punishing them. If,
instead of standing by, and giving their consent and sanction to all the laws
by which the weak man is first plundered, oppressed, and disheartened, and
then punished as a criminal, they would turn their attention to the duty of
defending his rights and improving his condition, and of thus strengthening
him, and enabling him to stand on his own feet, and withstand the temptations
that surround him, they would, I think, have little need to talk about laws
and prisons for either rum sellers or rum drinkers, or even any other class
of ordinary criminals.
If, in short, these men who are so anxious for the suppression of crime
would suspend, for a while, their calls upon the government for aid in
suppressing the crimes of individuals and would call upon the people for aid
in suppressing the crimes of the government, they would show both their
sincerity and good sense in a much stronger light than they do now. When the
laws shall all be so just and equitable as to make it possible for all men
and women to live honestly and virtuously and to make themselves comfortable
and happy, there will be much fewer occasions than now for charging them with
living dishonestly and viciously.
XXI
But it will be said, again, that the use of spirituous liquors tends to
poverty and thus to make men paupers, and burdensome to the taxpayers — and
that this is a sufficient reason why the sale of them should be prohibited.
There are various answers to this argument.
1. One answer is that if the fact
that the use of liquors tends to poverty and pauperism be a sufficient reason
for prohibiting the sale of them, it is equally a sufficient reason
for prohibiting the use of them; for it is the use, and not
the sale, that tends to poverty. The seller is, at most, merely an
accomplice of the drinker. And it is a rule of law, as well as of reason,
that if the principal in any act is not punishable, the accomplice cannot be.
2. A second answer to the argument
is, that if government has the right, and is bound, to prohibit any one act —
that is not criminal — merely because it is supposed to tend to
poverty, then, by the same rule, it has the right, and is bound, to prohibit
any and every other act — though not criminal — which, in the
opinion of the government, tends to poverty.
And, on this principle, the government would
not only have the right, but would be bound, to look into every
man's private affairs and every person's personal expenditures, and determine
as to which of them did, and which of them did not, tend to poverty — and to
prohibit and punish all of the former class. A man would have no right to
expend a cent of his own property, according to his own pleasure or judgment,
unless the legislature should be of the opinion that such expenditure would
not tend to poverty.
3. A third answer to the same
argument is that if a man does bring himself to poverty, and even to beggary
— either by his virtues or his vices — the government is under no
obligation whatever to take care of him, unless it pleases to do so. It may
let him perish in the street or depend upon private charity if it so pleases.
It can carry out its own free will and discretion in the matter; for it is
above all legal responsibility in such a case.
It is not, necessarily, any part of a
government's duty to provide for the poor. A government — that is, a
legitimate government — is simply a voluntary association of individuals, who
unite for such purposes, and only for such purposes, as suits them.
If taking care of the poor — whether they be virtuous or vicious — be not one
of those purposes, then the government, as a government, has no more
right, and is no more bound, to take care of them, than has or is a banking
company, or a railroad company.
Whatever moral claims a poor man —
whether he be virtuous or vicious — may have upon the charity of his
fellowmen, he has no legal claims upon them. He must depend wholly
upon their charity, if they so please. He cannot demand, as a legal
right, that they either feed or clothe him. And he has no more legal
or moral claims upon a government — which is but an association of
individuals — than he has upon the same, or any other individuals, in their
private capacity.
Inasmuch, then, as a poor man — whether
virtuous or vicious — has no more or other claims, legal or moral, upon a
government, for food or clothing, than he has upon private persons, a
government has no more right than a private person to control or prohibit the
expenditures or actions of an individual, on the ground that they tend to
bring him to poverty.
Mr. A, as an individual, has clearly
no right to prohibit any acts or expenditures of Mr. Z, through fear that
such acts or expenditures may tend to bring him (Z) to poverty, and that he
(Z) may, in consequence, at some future unknown time, come to him (A) in
distress, and ask charity. And if A has no such right as an individual
to prohibit any acts or expenditures on the part of Z, then government, which
is a mere association of individuals, can have no such right.
Certainly, no man who is compos mentis
holds his right to the disposal and use of his own property by any such
worthless tenure as that which would authorize any or all of his neighbors —
whether calling themselves a government or not — to interfere, and forbid him
to make any expenditures, except such as they might think would not tend to
poverty, and would not tend to ever bring him to them as a supplicant for
their charity.
Whether a man who is compos mentis
come to poverty through his virtues or his vices, no man, nor body of men,
can have any right to interfere with him, on the ground that their sympathy
may some time be appealed to in his behalf; because, if it should be appealed
to, they are at perfect liberty to act their own pleasure or discretion as to
complying with his solicitations.
As a consequence, the poor are left, to a great
extent, to depend upon private charity. In fact, they are often left to
suffer sickness, and even death, because neither public nor private charity
comes to their aid. How absurd, then, to say that government has a right to
control a man's use of his own property, through fear that he may sometime
come to poverty and ask charity.
4. Still a fourth answer to the
argument is that the great and only incentive which each individual man has
to labor, and to create wealth, is that he may dispose of it according to his
own pleasure or discretion, and for the promotion of his own happiness, and
the happiness of those whom he loves.[5]
Although a man may often, from inexperience or
want of judgment, expend some portion of the products of his labor
injudiciously, and so as not to promote his highest welfare, yet he learns
wisdom in this, as in all other matters, by experience — by his mistakes as
well as by his successes. And this is the only way in which he can learn
wisdom.
When he becomes convinced that he has made one foolish
expenditure, he learns thereby not to make another like it. And he must be
permitted to try his own experiments, and to try them to his own
satisfaction, in this as in all other matters; for otherwise he has no motive
to labor, or to create wealth at all.
Any man who is a man would rather be a savage
and be free, creating or procuring only such little wealth as he could
control and consume from day to day, than to be a civilized man, knowing how
to create and accumulate wealth indefinitely, and yet not permitted to use or
dispose of it, except under the supervision, direction, and dictation of a
set of meddlesome, superserviceable fools and tyrants, who, with no more
knowledge than himself, and perhaps with not half so much, should assume to
control him on the ground that he had not the right or the capacity to
determine for himself as to what he would do with the proceeds of his own
labor.
5. A fifth answer to the argument
is that if it be the duty of government to watch over the expenditures of any
one person — who is compos mentis and not criminal — to see what
ones tend to poverty, and what do not, and to prohibit and punish the former,
then, by the same rule, it is bound to watch over the expenditures of all
other persons, and prohibit and punish all that, in its judgment, tend to
poverty.
If such a principle were carried out
impartially, the result would be that all mankind would be so occupied in
watching each other's expenditures, and in testifying against, trying, and
punishing such as tended to poverty, that they would have no time left to
create wealth at all. Everybody capable of productive labor would either be
in prison, or be acting as judge, juror, witness, or jailer.
It would be impossible to create courts enough
to try, or to build prisons enough to hold, the offenders. All productive
labor would cease; and the fools that were so intent on preventing poverty
would not only all come to poverty, imprisonment, and starvation themselves,
but would bring everybody else to poverty, imprisonment, and starvation.
6. If it be said that a man may, at
least, be rightfully compelled to support his family, and, consequently, to
abstain from all expenditures that, in the opinion of the government, tend to
disable him to perform that duty, various answers might be given. But this
one is sufficient, viz.: that no man, unless a fool or a slave, would
acknowledge any family to be his, if that acknowledgment were to be made an
excuse, by the government, for depriving him, either of his personal liberty,
or the control of his property.
When a man is allowed his natural liberty, and
the control of his property, his family is usually, almost universally, the
great and paramount object of his pride and affection; and he will, not only
voluntarily, but as his highest pleasure, employ his best powers of mind and
body not merely to provide for them the ordinary necessaries and comforts of
life but to lavish upon them all the luxuries and elegancies that his labor
can procure.
A man enters into no moral or legal obligation
with his wife or children to do anything for them, except what he can do
consistently with his own personal freedom, and his natural right to control
his own property at his own discretion.
If a government can step in and say to a man
who is compos mentis and who is doing his duty to his family, as
he sees his duty, and according to his best judgment, however imperfect
that may be, "We (the government) suspect that you are not
employing your labor to the best advantage for your family; we suspect
that your expenditures, and your disposal of your property, are not so
judicious as they might be, for the interest of your family; and therefore we
(the government) will take you and your property under our special
surveillance, and prescribe to you what you may and may not do with yourself
and your property; and your family shall hereafter look to us (the
government), and not to you, for support" — if a government can do this,
all a man's pride, ambition, and affection, relative to this family, would be
crushed so far as it would be possible for human tyranny to crush them; and
he would either never have a family (whom he would publicly acknowledge to be
his), or he would risk both his property and his life in overthrowing such an
insulting, outrageous, and insufferable tyranny.
And any woman who would wish her husband — he
being compos mentis — to submit to such an unnatural insult and
wrong, is utterly undeserving of his affection, or of anything but his
disgust and contempt. And he would probably very soon cause her to understand
that, if she chose to rely on the government, for the support of herself and
her children, rather than on him, she must rely on the government alone.
XXII
Still another and all-sufficient answer to the argument that the use of
spirituous liquors tends to poverty, is that, as a general rule, it
puts the effect before the cause. It assumes that it is the use of the
liquors that causes the poverty, instead of its being the poverty that causes
the use of the liquors.
Poverty is the natural parent of nearly all the ignorance, vice, crime,
and misery there are in the world.[6]
Why is it that so large a portion of the laboring people of England are
drunken and vicious? Certainly not because they are by nature any worse than
other men.
But it is because their extreme and hopeless poverty keeps them in
ignorance and servitude, destroys their courage and self-respect, subjects
them to such constant insults and wrongs, to such incessant and bitter
miseries of every kind, and finally drives them to such despair, that the
short respite that drink or other vice affords them is, for the time being, a
relief. This is the chief cause of the drunkenness and other vices that
prevail among the laboring people of England.
If those laborers of England, who are now drunken and vicious, had had the
same chances and surroundings in life as the more fortunate classes have had;
if they had been reared in comfortable, and happy, and virtuous homes,
instead of squalid, and wretched, and vicious ones; if they had had
opportunities to acquire knowledge and property, and make themselves
intelligent, comfortable, happy, independent, and respected, and to secure to
themselves all the intellectual, social, and domestic enjoyments which honest
and justly rewarded industry could enable them to secure — if they could have
had all this, instead of being born to a life of hopeless, unrewarded toil,
with a certainty of death in the workhouse, they would have been as free from
their present vices and weaknesses as those who reproach them now are.
It is of no use to say that drunkenness, or any other vice, only adds to
their miseries; for such is human nature — the weakness of human nature, if
you please — that men can endure but a certain amount of misery before their
hope and courage fail and they yield to almost anything that promises present
relief or mitigation — though at the cost of still greater misery in the
future. To preach morality or temperance to such wretched persons, instead of
relieving their sufferings, or improving their conditions, is only insulting
their wretchedness.
Will those who are in the habit of attributing men's poverty to their
vices, instead of their vices to their poverty — as if every poor person, or
most poor persons, were specially vicious — tell us whether all the poverty
within the last year and a half[7] that
has been brought so suddenly — as it were in a moment — upon at least 20
millions of the people of the United States, were brought upon them as a
natural consequence, either of their drunkenness or of any other of their
vices? Was it their drunkenness or any other of their vices, that paralyzed,
as by a stroke of lightning, all the industries by which they lived, and
which had, but a few days before, been in such prosperous activity?
Was it their vices that turned the adult portion of those 20 millions out
of doors without employment, compelled them to consume their little
accumulations, if they had any, and then to become beggars — beggars for
work, and, failing in this, beggars for bread? Was it their vices that, all
at once, and without warning, filled the homes of so many of them with want,
misery, sickness, and death? No. Clearly it was neither the drunkenness, nor
any other vices, of these laboring people, that brought upon them all this
ruin and wretchedness. And if it was not, what was it?
This is the problem that must be answered; for it is one that is
repeatedly occurring and constantly before us and that cannot be put aside.
In fact, the poverty of the great body of mankind, the world over, is the
great problem of the world. That such extreme and nearly universal poverty
exists all over the world, and has existed through all past generations,
proves that it originates in causes which the common human nature of those
who suffer from it has not hitherto been strong enough to overcome. But these
sufferers are at least beginning to see these causes and are becoming
resolute to remove them, let it cost what it may.
And those who imagine that they have nothing to do but to go on
attributing the poverty of the poor to their vices, and preaching to them
against their vices, will ere long wake up to find that the day for all such
talk is past. And the question will then be, not what are men's vices, but
what are their rights?